Some people believe that
the federal government of the United States is divided into three separate but
equal branches. Yet, one of those branches – the judicial -- gets to establish
what the Constitution supposedly means (even though the Philadelphia Constitution
does not necessarily entitle the courts to be the determiners of that sort of
meaning) , and, therefore, one wonders in what way the three branches can be
said to be equal to one another.
Anyone who gets to have
the last word on what can and can’t be done is hardly on the same level as
those who must get approval to proceed on with their various spheres of
activity. The real head of
government in the United States is the judiciary rather than either the executive
or the legislature because what the judiciary decides – at least on the level
of the Supreme Court – is, contrary to the belief of Harry Truman, where the
buck actually stops.
Notwithstanding Abraham
Lincoln’s attempt to arrest the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court, the
executive and legislative branches are answerable to the Supreme Court … not
the other way around. Except for needing to be appointed by the President and
confirmed by the Senate, as well as act in accordance with principles of “good
behavior” – whatever that means -- the members of the Supreme Court are not
answerable to either the executive office or the legislature … although the
latter two branches are answerable to the Supreme Court.
The asymmetry of the
relationship between, on the one hand, the Supreme Court, and, on the other
hand, the executive and the legislative branches is quite remarkable given that
the Philadelphia Constitution never clearly established what the precise
character of the role of the Supreme Court should be. Article III says that
judicial power, of some kind, should “be vested in one Supreme Court and in
such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and
establish,” but the process of ‘vesting’ remains unclear … as is the nature of
the ‘judicial power’ that is to be so vested.
Section 2 of Article III
indicates that “judicial power shall extend to all cases in law and
equity, arising under this Constitution.” In addition, the same judicial powers
shall be extended to: the laws of the United States; all treaties made
under the authority of such laws; cases involving ambassadors, public
ministers, and consuls; admiralty and maritime issues; controversies to which
the United States is a party; disputes involving two or more states; cases
between any given state and the citizen of another state; conflicts between
citizens of the same state which involve land granted by other states, as well
as cases between a state or its citizens and some foreign country or
citizens/subjects of such a country.
However, the precise
meaning of how judicial power will be “extended” to any of the foregoing
possibilities is not further elaborated upon in the Philadelphia Constitution.
Article III, Section 2, Paragraph 2 of the Philadelphia Constitution does
indicate that the Supreme Court will have original jurisdiction in all cases
involving states, ambassadors, public ministers, and consuls, while the Supreme
Court retains only appellate jurisdiction in all other cases.
What ensues from either
‘original’ or ‘appellate’ jurisdiction is not specified in the Philadelphia
Constitution. Number 78 of the collection of essays that have come to be known,
collectively, as The Federalist Papers
(written by Hamilton, Madison, and Jay for various newspapers during the
ratification process in New York State) does develop a perspective concerning
the idea of judicial review in relation to the judiciary, but The Federalist Papers are not part of
the Constitution.
Some people might wish to
argue that the position concerning judicial review that was put forth in Number
78 of The Federalist Papers gives
expression to the intent of some of the Founders/Framers. Consequently – or so
the argument might go -- the views contained in Federalist-Number 78 should carry a special weight with respect to
how anyone envisions the activity of the judiciary.
The foregoing argument
might be more credible if there were evidence that all – or a substantial
majority -- of the participants in the Philadelphia Convention shared the
perspective put forth in Federalist-Number
78. However, if this had been the case, then one might have anticipated that at
least a paragraph, or two, of Article III of the Philadelphia Constitution
might have introduced the idea of judicial review and provided an overview of
how that activity would serve as the process through which the meaning of the
Constitution is to be confirmed or established.
Since nothing concerning
the idea of judicial review appears in the Philadelphia Constitution, then what
the intent of Alexander Hamilton (the author of Number 78) might have been with
respect to the functioning of the judiciary – especially the Supreme Court – is
really neither here nor there. Madison, the so-called father of the
Constitution, might have agreed with Hamilton concerning the contents of Number
78, but, again, there is no indication that the majority of the participants in
the Philadelphia Convention – or, perhaps more importantly, the majority of the
participants of the ratification process -- shared such a point of view, and,
therefore, there is no really plausible argument which demonstrates that what
Madison and Hamilton might have thought about the idea of judicial review
should carry any special constitutional weight.
Despite the fact that Federalist-Number 78 really has little,
or no, standing with respect to the issue of determining what the function of
the Supreme Court is within the framework of the Philadelphia Constitution,
nevertheless, examining that essay might prove to be of some value. So, let’s
take a brief tour of that essay.
Federalist-Number 78 indicates there are three questions concerning the
functioning of the judiciary that need to be answered with respect to the
proposed constitution (the Philadelphia Constitution had not, yet, been
ratified by the required number of states at the time the Number 78 essay was written).
The three questions involved: (1) the process through which judges will be
appointed; (2) the issue of tenure or length of appointment; (3) the manner in
which the courts will be partitioned and how those courts will interact with
one another.
The first and third of
the aforementioned questions are barely touched upon by Hamilton in Federalist-Number 78. The second
question occupies most of the rest of the essay even though many of the ideas
in that discussion revolve around arguments involving: judicial discretion, the
role of the judiciary, and the issue of precedents. Those arguments are, then,
used to defend the idea of having an independent judiciary that, once
appointed, becomes permanent.
During the course of
examining the issue of tenure, Hamilton maintained that among the three
branches of government, the judiciary should be considered to be the least
dangerous to the people. More specifically, whereas, on the one hand, the
legislative branch held the purse strings, as well as possessed the capacity to
determine the rights of every citizen through the laws it made, and while the
executive had the authority to command the power of the sword, on the other
hand, the judiciary had no force or will of its own since all the judiciary
could do was exercise judgment, with no capacity to enforce its decisions.
Hamilton’s foregoing
argument seems to be rather unconvincing. After all, if the people do not
comply with the executive’s wielding of the sword or the legislature’s issuing
of laws, then the executive and the legislature have as little power as he
claims is the case in relation to the judiciary.
Just as people are
necessary to carry out the directives of the executive and the legislature,
people also are necessary to carry out the directives of the judiciary. Without
co-operation and compliance by the people, none of the branches of government
will be functional.
The executive, the
legislature, and the judiciary have as much -- or as little -- power as the
people concede to them. If the people accept – actively or passively -- the
role of the judiciary, then one cannot necessarily argue that the judiciary has
less power than either the executive or the legislature or that the judiciary
is necessarily less of a threat to the liberties of the people than the other
two branches of government are … a lot depends on what the judiciary does with
the power that has been delegated to it.
According to Hamilton,
the judiciary has “no influence over either the purse or the sword.” If this
were true, then, presumably, this means that whatever the function of the
judiciary might be, the judiciary could not make judgments affecting how
Congress spent money or how the executive wielded the sword.
Subsequent events have
proven Hamilton to be wrong with respect to the degree of potential influence
which the judiciary has over the executive and the legislature. If nothing
else, time has demonstrated that Hamilton didn’t really understand the nature
of the beast that the essays in The
Federalist Papers were attempting to bring into existence.
Nothing like the
Philadelphia Constitution had been attempted before. Consequently, most of the
material in The Federalist Papers was
entirely theoretical -- that is, those essays gave expression to the ‘best
guesses’ of how people like Hamilton, Madison, and Jay thought the process of
governance might unfold
In any event, the rule-making dimension
of Congress is not mentioned in the foregoing quote concerning Hamilton’s
contention that the judiciary has: “no influence over either the purse or the
sword.” Therefore, one is uncertain whether, or not, the absence of that facet
of Congressional activity in the indicated quote from Federalist-Number 78 carries any implications for how the judiciary
might affect and influence the functioning of the executive or the legislative
branches.
Hamilton continues on
with his argument by stating that the judiciary was not only the weakest of the
three branches, but, as well, he indicates that the judiciary would never be
able to mount any sort of successful attack against either of the other two
branches of government. However, Hamilton did warn that the judiciary would
have to protect itself against attempts by the executive and legislative
branches to undermine its authority.
Federalist-Number 78 held that as long as the judiciary is kept separate from
the executive and legislative branches, then the people have nothing to fear
from the judicial branch with respect to liberties. A threat to the liberty of
citizens would only become a possibility if the judiciary came under the sway
of executive and/or legislative power.
Apparently, one of the
themes relevant to the exercise of judicial power is ensuring that the limits
placed on the legislative branches by the Constitution would be upheld. Hamilton
specifically mentions several examples (coming from: Article I, Section 9,
Paragraph 3) – namely, bills of attainder (the process of legislatively
singling out a person or group for punishment without benefit of a trial) and
ex post facto laws (e.g., passing laws that criminalize previous acts that were
not criminal at the time they were performed), and Hamilton claims that
maintaining such limitations are appropriate issues for the judiciary to
handle.
Hamilton seems oblivious
to the discrepancy between what he believes to be a proper role for the
judiciary – namely, upholding the constitutional limits that had been placed on
the legislative branches – and his earlier contention that the judicial branch
was the weakest of the three branches. If the judicial branch is as weak as he
claims, then how does that branch propose to restrain the legislature from
exceeding its constitutionally approved sphere of activity?
According to Hamilton,
fulfilling the foregoing function might require the judiciary to decide in a
given case whether, or not, the legislature was violating the Constitutional
prohibition against bills of attainder and ex post facto laws. Moreover, by
implication, this sort of decision process might require the judiciary to
interpret the structural character of the conceptual boundaries concerning those
issues – that is, whether, or not, some given act of the legislature was a
violation of Constitutional prohibitions involving bills of attainder and ex
post facto laws.
If so, then the problem
becomes whether, or not, such a process of interpretation involves the exercise
of discretionary degrees of freedom by the judiciary. If bills of attainder or
ex post facto laws are rules that are fairly linear and consistent in their
sphere of applicability, then in accordance with the requirements of legal
positivism, one merely has to determine what the ‘facts’ of a given case are
and compare those facts with the character of the Constitutional provisions and,
then, determine the nature of the relationship between the ‘facts’ and those
provisions.
If, on the other hand,
bills of attainder or ex post facto laws are somewhat non-linear in character,
then the judiciary might have to exercise interpretive or hermeneutical
discretion concerning whether a given Constitutional prohibition was, or was
not, violated. Under those sorts of circumstances, one would have to try (as Ronald Dworkin did, for example, in: Taking Rights Seriously) to come up with a defensible theory of interpretation or
hermeneutics concerning how discretion was to be exercised in such cases.
Hamilton claimed that it
was the duty of the courts to: “declare all acts contrary to the manifest tenor
of the Constitution void.” Unfortunately, this kind of language is not found
anywhere in the Constitution.
Furthermore, even if this
kind of language had appeared in the Constitution, one would still be faced
with a problem. What is meant by the idea of: “the manifest tenor of the
Constitution”?
Does the Constitution
have a manifest tenor? In a previous posting (http://anab-whitehouse.blogspot.com/2014/01/constitutional-framers-founders-and.html) I suggested that in many respects – but not necessarily all -- there is no
manifest tenor inherent in the Constitution.
There were as many
understandings concerning the nature of the Constitution as there were
participants in the Philadelphia Convention. There were as many understandings
concerning the nature of the Constitution as there were participants in the
ratification process … which is one of the reasons why so many delegates to the
ratification conventions wanted to introduce amendments in order to protect
against possible problems manifesting themselves in the future as a result of
the ambiguities that were perceived by many to be present in the
Constitution-as-written.
To be sure, there are
likely to be a variety of areas within the Constitution on which there might
have been a general consensus concerning the “manifest tenor” of that document.
However, assuming that there is a similar ‘manifest tenor’ which can be
extended to the entire Constitution is another matter – especially in light of
the fact there have been so many 5-4 and 6-3 decisions that have been rendered
during the history of the Supreme Court.
One of the reasons why
there is so much partisan bickering concerning the confirmation of judges has
less to do with the possible “manifest tenor” of the Constitution than it does
with wanting to ensure that the judges who are confirmed will interpret the
Constitution in a manner that is resonant with the political and economic
interests of those who command the majority position in the Senate. If there
really were a “manifest tenor” of the Constitution, there would be only one way
to understand the nature and meaning of the Constitution, and, yet, no one has
been able to put forth an unassailable case in that respect.
One needs to go no
further than the Preamble to the Constitution to understand that the meaning of
the Constitution is hopelessly ambiguous. No one – in government or beyond –
can put forth a case that is defensible, beyond a reasonable doubt, with
respect to what is meant by: ‘establishing justice,’ ‘insuring domestic
tranquility,’ ‘providing for the common defense,’ ‘promoting the general
welfare,’ and ‘securing the blessings of liberty to ourselves and our
posterity.’
Everyone has theories
about the foregoing ideas. No one has proof beyond a reasonable doubt that his
or her theories accurately reflect the ‘manifest tenor’ of the Constitution …
or, perhaps more importantly, accurately reflect the nature of reality.
Hamilton argued that
elected representatives should not be judges in their own causes with respect
to what was, and was not, appropriate with respect to the meaning of the
Constitution. Consequently, Hamilton believed that the role of the judiciary
was to act on behalf of the people by limiting the activity of the legislature
and restraining the latter through demarcating the proper boundaries within
which the legislature was entitled to operate with respect to the enumerated
powers that had been granted to it via the Constitution.
For Hamilton:
“Interpretation of the law is the proper and peculiar province of the courts”.
Yet, if there is a “manifest tenor to the Constitution,” then what need is
there for judicial interpretation?
Stated somewhat
differently, one might ask: If only judges are capable of interpreting the law
– since, according to Hamilton, it is their proper and peculiar province --
then one wonders just how manifest the tenor of the Constitution actually is?
Alternatively, if judges are the only ones capable of understanding the
manifest tenor of the Constitution, then why do they disagree with one another?
Wherever there are
ambiguities present in the Constitution (and there are many – for example, what
is meant by the “necessary and proper” clause in the last paragraph of Section
8 in Article I), judicial discretion will enter the picture. Whenever judicial
discretion becomes necessary, one needs to be able to demonstrate that a given
mode of exercising that kind of discretion is defensible beyond all reasonable
doubt … otherwise the exercise of that sort of discretion will be entirely
arbitrary.
Hamilton considered a
constitution to be a fundamental form of law. Furthermore, he maintained that
it was the function of the courts to determine what the meaning of that sort of
fundamental law is, as well as to determine the meaning of whatever laws might
be issued by the legislature.
If the courts determine
that there is some sort of irreconcilable discrepancy between the meaning of
the Constitution and the meaning of the laws that are forthcoming from the
legislature, then, according to Hamilton, preference should be given to the
meaning of the Constitution. He equates the intention of the people with the
meaning of the Constitution and indicates that both should be preferred to the
intention of legislative agents.
Unfortunately, the people
did not write the Constitution. Therefore, there is no reason why the intention
of the people and the meaning of the Constitution should be considered to be
synonymous with one another.
Of course, attempting to
equate the intention of the people with the meaning of the Constitution might
be an allusion to the resolution passed by the signatories to the Philadelphia
Constitution that the people should ratify the Philadelphia Constitution rather
than the Continental Congress and the state legislatures. If so, then the
argument might be that the meaning of the Constitution gave expression to the
intention of the people when they ratified it.
However, many segments of
“We the People” – even among those who voted to ratify the Philadelphia
Constitution – had reservations concerning the meaning of certain aspects of
the Constitution. Consequently, one is not necessarily justified in equating
the intention of the people with the meaning of the Constitution as Hamilton
seeks to do in Federalist-Number 78.
According to Hamilton,
the capacity of the judiciary to interpret the meaning of the Constitution did
not make the judiciary superior to the legislature, but, rather, merely
indicated that the will of the people was superior to either the judiciary or
the legislature. When the judiciary determines the meaning of the Constitution,
then, from Hamilton’s perspective, the courts are merely acting in the service
of the will and intention of the people and demonstrating that the will and
intention of ‘We the People’ is superior to that of the legislature.
There seems to be a
substantial amount of sophistry in Hamilton’s foregoing argument. On the
surface, his mode of reasoning seems attractive because it tries to reduce the
meaning of the Constitution to the will and intention of ‘We the People’, yet
‘We the People’ did not formulate the Constitution, and, more importantly,
there were too many problems inherent in the ratification process to try to
justifiably claim that the ratified Constitution gave expression to the
intention, will, and meanings of ‘We the People’ with respect to the issue of
governance.
Moreover, Hamilton
believes that only courts have the “peculiar province” to be able to interpret
and understand the manifest tenor of the Constitution, and, therefore, the will
and intention of ‘We the People.’ Consequently, one wonders why ‘We the People’
do not have the capacity to understand their intention and will independently
of the judiciary … or, why ‘We the People’ need someone to adjudicate such
matters if the manifest tenor of the Constitution is as manifest as Hamilton
claims it is?
Hamilton goes on to argue
that the exercise of judicial discretion will always be a matter of courts
generating fair constructions -- “so far as they can” – with respect to, on the
one hand, laws that are in apparent conflict with one another but are capable
of being reconciled with each other or, on the other hand, laws that are not
reconcilable with each other but one of which can be demonstrated to be
consistent with the fundamental law of the Constitution. Hamilton doesn’t
specify: What the criteria are for determining what constitutes a ‘fair
construction’ or how far courts will be able to generate such constructions, or
why one should suppose that one of two conflicting laws will be capable of
being demonstrate to be consistent with the Constitution – or how one
accomplishes this -- when it is possible that neither law might be all that
consistent with the Constitution … a lot depends on the criteria of
‘consistency.’
All one gets from
Hamilton’s essay is the idea or possibility that ‘somehow’ the exercise of
judicial discretion will lead to a decision or judgment that will serve the
intention and will of the people. There is no proof of this … only the
theoretical assertion.
Federalist-Number 78 does not disclose the structural character of the process
of judicial discretion. Federalist-Number
78 does not disclose what constitutes a ‘fair construction’ or what the
criteria of ‘fairness’ are for such a construction. Federalist-Number 78 does not disclose whether, or not, the
exercise of judicial discretion really gives expression to the intention and
will of the people. Federalist-Number
78 does not disclose what the criteria are for determining whether two laws are
capable of being reconciled with one another in a way that is consistent with
the fundamental law of the Constitution, or what the criteria are for
demonstrating that one law, rather than another, is consistent with the
Constitution. Federalist-Number 78
does not disclose why -- if the “manifest tenor of the Constitution” is really
manifest -- only judges are capable of understanding that tenor.
Hamilton attempts to
claim that concerns about judges substituting their own will for the meaning of
law carry no weight. However, his reasoning concerning this issue seems rather
suspect.
In effect, Hamilton
argues that if judges, like legislators, were to substitute their own likes and
dislikes (i.e., will) in place of the actual requirements of the fundamental
law of the Constitution (i.e., judgment), then this would be an argument
against having judges at all since the latter individuals would be succumbing
to the same sort of error as is committed by those legislators who follow their
own likes and dislikes (will) rather than comply with the requirements of the
Constitution. This argument is valid as far as it goes but doesn’t explain why judges
would not be vulnerable to preferring their own likes and dislikes (i.e., their
will) in the same way that legislators are vulnerable.
Toward the latter part of
Federalist-Number 78, Hamilton
explores the issue of having to find candidates for the judiciary who have the
requisite technical skills, as well individuals who will have the necessary
integrity to overcome the natural tendency of many individuals to prefer their
likes and dislikes to considered judgment, but the discussion is very general.
Hamilton has almost nothing to say about how one identifies those kinds of
individuals.
Hamilton indicates there
is a difference between ‘judicial will’ and ‘judicial judgment.’ Unfortunately,
he doesn’t explain what the precise character of that difference is other
than to suggest that judgment
will comply with the requirements of the fundamental law of the Constitution,
whereas will does not comply with that law.
Consequently, contrary to
Hamilton’s claims in Federalist-Number
78, the possibility of jurists substituting their will concerning the
Constitution does carry weight. Although Article IV, Section 4 of the
Constitution guarantees a republican form of government to every state, there
is no way to determine whether any given exercise of judicial discretion is
actually giving faithful expression to that kind of a guarantee.
Hamilton assumes – or
hopes – the foregoing will be the case. Nonetheless, he can’t prove that this
is how things will actually turn out because he has failed to establish a clear
set of criteria for demonstrating when ‘judicial judgment’ is being exercised
rather than ‘judicial will.’
Toward the latter part of
Federalist-Number 78, Hamilton states: “It has been frequently remarked, with
great propriety, that a voluminous code of laws is one of the inconveniences
necessarily connected with the advantages of a free government. To avoid an arbitrary
discretion in the courts, it is indispensable that they should be bound down by
strict rules and precedents, which serve to define and point out their duty in
every particular case that comes before them; and it will readily be conceived
from the variety of controversies which grow out of the folly and wickedness of
mankind, that the records of those precedents must unavoidably swell to a very
considerable bulk, and must demand long and laborious study to acquire a
competent knowledge of them. Hence it is that there can be but few men in the
society who will have sufficient skill in the laws to qualify them for the
stations of judges.” However, Hamilton does not stipulate what it means to “be
bound down by strict rules and precedents” or why the manner of being ‘bound
down’ should be in accordance with some rules and precedents rather than
others.
Moreover, if those sorts
of “strict rules and precedents … serve to define and point out their [i.e.,
the courts] duty in every particular case that comes before them,” then what
need is there for the sort of judicial discretion which Hamilton claims is the
“peculiar province” of courts? In addition, if a “long and laborious study” of
precedents should be required in order “to acquire a competent knowledge of”
those precedents in order to be able to come to know one’s duty in any
particular case, then what happened to the “manifest tenor of the
Constitution?”
Hamilton argued earlier
in Federalist-Number 78 that: “the
prior act of a superior ought to be preferred to the subsequent act of an
inferior and subordinate authority; and that accordingly, whenever a particular
statute contravenes the Constitution, it will be the duty of the judicial
tribunals to adhere to the latter and disregard the former.” If this is the
case, then what need is there of precedents since the “manifest tenor” of the
fundamental law of the Constitution should always have precedence over any
other kind of secondary judgment – i.e., precedent – developed in accordance
with this or that statute?
What function do
precedents have if the Constitution is the mother of all precedents? If
subsequent precedents draw out the meaning of the Constitution in greater
detail or specificity, then, perhaps, Hamilton was wrong about the “manifest
tenor” of the Constitution, and irrespective of whether he was right or wrong
on this latter issue, one still doesn’t really have any clear sense of what is
meant by the idea of the Constitution’s “manifest tenor” or how one goes about
determining whether, or not, subsequent precedents are consistent with that
tenor.
Many of the ideas which
Hamilton introduced in Federalist-Number
78 were – as pointed out toward the beginning of this discussion -- directed
toward supporting the argument that the tenure of jurists should be permanent
as long as “good behavior” was in evidence. Hamilton believed that a judiciary
which had tenured permanence would best serve the interests of the people
against possible violations of Constitutional limits by the legislature and, in
addition, would be independent of the executive branch as well.
Unfortunately, there are
many questions that arise during the course of Federalist-Number 78 in relation to such ideas as: The manifest
tenor of the Constitution; the meaning of the fundamental law of the
Constitution; judicial discretion; fair construction; judicial will; and the
role of precedents. Hamilton provides no way to answer the foregoing questions
in a non-arbitrary way … and, yet, Hamilton was quite concerned with avoiding “arbitrary discretion in the
courts.”
Consequently, in view of
the many unanswered questions and ambiguities that exist in conjunction with Federalist-Number 78, one can’t help but
feel a certain amount of discomfort with the thought that, according to
Hamilton, members of the judiciary should have permanent tenure and, thereby,
be in a position to – possibly -- impose arbitrary interpretations of the
Constitution upon citizens (which is equivalent to the idea of “judicial will”)
rather than -- allegedly -- giving expression to the intention and will of ‘We
the People’ by making proper judgments – whatever they are -- concerning the
‘manifest tenor’ of the Constitution. Instead of mounting an argument in
defense of the idea of permanent tenure for the judiciary, Hamilton’s failure
to clearly and adequately address certain issues concerning the judiciary in Federalist-Number 78 tends to bring the
idea of permanent tenure into question.
In Federalist-Number 83
Hamilton refers to some general guidelines for interpreting the law while he
addresses the question of whether, or not, the Philadelphia Constitution’s
provisions for trial by jury in criminal cases automatically excludes the idea
of trials by jury in civil cases. At one point in the essay, Hamilton
stipulates that the process of interpreting the law is just a matter of
applying rules of common sense that have been adopted by the courts during the
construction of laws.
One person’s idea of
common sense is often antithetical to the thinking of others who might consider
that the former person’s idea to be doing something other than making ‘sense’ …
common or otherwise. Moreover, that which might have seemed commonsensical
during the construction of certain laws might not be considered to be so
commonsensical when subsequent jurists engage those laws and attempt to
interpret the possible meanings of those laws.
Hamilton goes on to say,
with respect to the issue of interpreting a constitution, that: “the natural
and obvious sense of its provisions, apart from any technical rules, is the
true criterion of construction.” Like the issue of common sense, what one
person considers to be: “the natural and obvious sense” of something (e.g., a
law or constitution) will not necessarily reflect what another individual
considers to be “the natural and obvious sense” of that ‘same something’ … and
the history of judicial interpretation tends to support the foregoing
contention.
What is considered to be
commonsensical, natural, or obvious takes place in a certain context of
understanding. Different frameworks of understanding often give expression to
different ideas about what is commonsensical, natural, and obvious.
The relationship between
Madison and Hamilton gives clear expression to the foregoing point. More
specifically, during the drafting of the Philadelphia Constitution, as well as
during the writing of the essays that collectively came to be known as The Federalist Papers, Madison and
Hamilton were conceptual allies, and, yet, not very long after ratification of
that constitution had been completed, the two individuals became philosophical
enemies with respect to what they each considered to be commonsensical, natural
, and obvious with respect to the practical application of the Philadelphia
Constitution in relation to the issue of governance -- for example, their
radically different opinions concerning the constitutionality of a national
bank in which Madison argued against that idea on the basis of, among other
things, a narrow interpretation of
the necessary and proper clause of the last paragraph of Article I, Section 8,
while Hamilton argued in favor of such a bank on the basis of, among other
things, a broader interpretation of that same clause.
-----
Between 1789 and 1801,
the Supreme Court made only a small number of decisions that might be
considered to have some degree of importance. In fact, the role of the Court
seemed to be so peripheral to the functioning of government that John Jay, the
first Chief Justice of the Supreme Court, declined John Adams’ offer to have
Jay continue on as the head of the Court because Jay felt that the Court would
never attain the sort of gravitas that would enable the Court to play an
influential and effective role in governance.
Adams appointed John
Marshall to become the new Chief Justice. Marshall held that position for 35
years, and over the course of those three and a half decades, Justice Marshall
proceeded to construct a hermeneutical or interpretive perspective that gave
expression to how he believed the Court ought to engage its constitutionally
granted powers.
At the heart of Justice
Marshall’s philosophy is the belief that the judiciary should exercise its
constitutionally granted authority in order to give effect to the will of the
law rather than to the will of the judges. This is the same sort of point that
Hamilton made in the previously discussed Federalist-Number
78 when he distinguished between the will and judgment of the court and
indicated that only the latter process – that is, judgment – would be able to
uncover the true meaning of a law or constitution.
Justice Marshall’s
approach to understanding the nature of law leaves one with the same kinds of
problems with which Hamilton left us earlier on. What are the criteria – and
how are those criteria or their application to be justified – for determining
what constitutes the ‘will of the law’ rather than the ‘will of a jurist’ or
judge?
According to Justice
Marshall in Brown v. Maryland (1827),
when a jurist seeks to construct the meaning of this or that clause of the
Constitution: “it is proper to take a view of the literal meaning of the words
to be expounded, of their connection with other words, and of the general
objects to be accomplished by the prohibitory clause, or by the grant of
power.” Whose “literal meaning of the words to be expounded” is to be accepted?
Whose understanding of “their connection with other words” is to be adopted?
Whose interpretation of the “general objects to be accomplished” or powers to
be granted is to govern how a jurist reaches his or her judgment concerning the
alleged meaning of the Constitution? More importantly, how does one justify,
beyond a reasonable doubt: Accepting one sense of the literal meaning of a set
of words rather than some other sense of those words; or, the adopting of one understanding
rather than some other understanding concerning the alleged relationship of
those words to other words; or, the use of one interpretation rather than some
other interpretation in relation to the nature of the “general objects to be
accomplished” or powers to be granted?
Justice Marshall says
that it is proper to proceed in the way he indicates, but he doesn’t justify
why such a methodology is “proper”. Like Ronald Dworkin’s fictional Hercules,
Justice Marshall accepts the idea that the Constitution is, in part, settled
law – for example, that the judiciary has been given power to engage the law,
and Marshall is intent on mapping out the nature of that power, but the issue
remains whether Justice Marshall was undertaking that project out of judicial
will or judicial judgment.
The Philadelphia
Constitution cannot serve as the source of its own authority without running
into a circular argument which is entirely arbitrary. The source of authority
for the Constitution – however it might be interpreted – lies beyond the
horizons of that document, and this fact was recognized by the Founders/Framers
when they sought to root the authority of the Constitution in the will of ‘We
the People’ via the process of ratification.
However, if the
ratification process was flawed in substantial ways – and some of these flaws
were outlined in a previous posting (http://anab-whitehouse.blogspot.com/2014/07/the-ratification-game-how-power.html) – then, one cannot automatically assume that the
ratification process has the capacity to provide the sort of authority which
could justify or sanction the legitimacy of the Constitution. If this is the
case, then granting jurists the power to establish the meaning of a document –
i.e., the Constitution – through this or that methodology really might not be
as “proper” as Justice Marshall supposes because the underlying authority for
doing so is questionable.
Even if one were to grant
– for the purposes of argument – that the Philadelphia Constitution gave
expression to a legitimate source of authority via the process of ratification
for those who participated in such a process, nonetheless, the issue of
propriety concerning methodology does not end. However legitimate a given form
of governance (e.g., the Philadelphia Constitution) might be for those who – we
will assume – authorized it through the process of ratification, why should
such an arrangement be binding on people living several hundred years later who
had no role in either the drafting or ratification of that arrangement?
Will it still be “proper
to take a view of the literal meaning of the words to be expounded, of their
connection with other words, and of the general objects to be accomplished by
the prohibitory clause, or by the grant of power”? What do: The literal meaning
of such words, or their connections with other words, or the general objects to
be accomplished, or the powers to be granted, have to do with people living
more than two hundred years later
-- even if the meanings of
those words, their connections, the general objects, and powers could be
determined without controversy?
Justice Marshall understood
that the task of interpretation would be a challenge given that it took place
within a context complicated by the existence of conflicting federal powers, as
well as political/economic interests that varied from state to state.
Nevertheless, as complicating as the foregoing factors might be, the most
problematic complications were given expression through the Preamble to the
Constitution that, supposedly, outlined the purposes for which the Constitution
had been constructed.
More specifically, all the
allegedly “literal” meanings of words and their connection with: Other words,
prohibitory clauses, and grants of power, have to be filtered through the
Preamble. Yet, without a clear understanding of what is meant by the idea of:
‘establishing justice,’ ‘insuring domestic tranquility,’ ‘providing for the
common defense,’ ‘promoting the general welfare,’ or ‘securing the blessings of
liberty,’ then irrespective of whatever legal methodology one judges to be
“proper” to guide one’s process of understanding or interpreting, among other
things, “the literal meaning” of words in the Constitution, nevertheless, one
is just arbitrarily engaging that document.
In Gibbons v. Ogden (1824), Justice Marshall claimed that: “It is a
well-settled rule that the objects for which it [a power] was given, especially
when those objects are expressed in the instrument itself, should have great
influence in the construction.” Yet, even though the Preamble to the
Constitution states the objects for which the various powers of the
Constitution have been granted, one is uncertain what the nature of the
influence of those objects is on the construction of the meaning of the
Constitution because one doesn’t necessarily know what is meant by words such
as: ‘justice,’ ‘defense, ’tranquility,’ ‘welfare’, or ‘liberty.’
In Ogden v. Saunders (1827), Justice Marshall stated that “the
intention of the instrument must prevail.” He went on to claim that one derived
the nature of such intention from the words which are used in a given instrument
and that those words were to be understood in the way in which those for whom
the instrument had been constructed – i.e., the people – generally understood
those words. Furthermore, Justice Marshall stipulated that the provisions of those
instruments were: “Neither to be restricted into insignificance, nor extended
to objects not comprehended in them, nor contemplated by its framers.”
What does it mean to
neither restrict the meaning of something into insignificance, nor to extend
that meaning beyond what had been contemplated by those who constructed a given
instrument of governance? How do we know that the instrument was constructed in
accordance with the manner in which the generality of people understand the
words employed in such an instrument? How does one determine what the
generality of people understand the meaning of certain words to be within the
context of a legal instrument such as a constitution? Who is to be considered a
framer, and what if not everyone who helped frame an instrument necessarily
spoke out about the nature of what they contemplated as they voted for that
kind of an instrument? What if the intention of the framers – even if that
intention could be identified – did not accurately reflect the will of the
people, and how would one set about determining whether, or not, the framer’s
intention properly reflected the will of the people?
When Justice Marshall
issued his decision in Marbury v. Madison
(1803), he maintained that the people had “an original right” to establish
a form of governance that in their opinion likely would lead to their
collective happiness. Moreover, he believed America had come into being with
such a right and goal in mind.
However, according to
Justice Marshall, exercising the “original right” required a great deal of
effort and, therefore, he considered that sort of a process something which
neither can -- nor ought to -- be done frequently. Consequently, he held that:
“The principles … so established, are deemed fundamental. And as the authority
from which they proceed is supreme, and can seldom act, they are deemed to be
permanent.”
There are several
problems inherent in the foregoing perspective of Justice Marshall. First, to
claim that the people have “an original right” with respect to developing a
form of governance that is conducive to their happiness is one thing, but to
claim that what took place in the Philadelphia Convention is an appropriate
expression of that ‘original right’ might be quite another matter.
The 55 delegates who
attended the Philadelphia Convention of 1787 were not a representative sample
of the American people. With the exception of Alexander Hamilton, Roger
Sherman, and, to a degree, Benjamin Franklin, the individuals who attended that
convention were not self-made men but came from families that were fairly
wealthy and influential in Colonial America.
Thomas Paine, who did not
attend the convention, represented a radicalized part of society involving both
sides of the ocean that regularly explored an array of political and economic
issues in the taverns and teahouses of the Atlantic world. The perspective of
those individuals concerning issues involving: freedom, rights, governance,
property, and commercial fairness were -- relative to the ideas being
considered by the delegates to the Philadelphia Convention -- quite different
in many respects.
The Philadelphia
Convention gave expression to one possibility concerning how the ‘original
right’ to which Justice Marshall referred might be exercised. However, that
effort was skewed by the backgrounds, interests, inclinations, and purposes of
the people who participated in the aforementioned convention.
In an earlier posting, I indicated
that the Philadelphia Convention might have had a very different outcome if
certain people who did not attend that assembly – namely, Patrick Henry, Thomas
Paine, Thomas Jefferson, William Findley, Samuel Adams, and Richard Henry Lee –
had been able to collaborate with those individuals who did attend the
Philadelphia Convention but were disgruntled, in one way or another, with the
nature of that assembly … individuals such as: George Mason, Elbridge Gerry,
Edmond Randolph, John Lansing, Jr., Robert Yates, and Luther Martin. Moreover,
what about the many individuals in America who were never even considered as
possible participants for the Philadelphia Convention?
Thomas Paine was not an
isolated individual. Rather, he was just one of the participants in the radical
discussions that had been taking place in Atlantic Europe before he even came
to America, and he continued on with those tavern-based discussions when he
arrived in America. Consequently, to suppose that people like James Madison and
Alexander Hamilton – or other members from their social, educational, and
economic background -- were the only individuals who were thinking about issues
of governance, rights, liberty, and justice (or were even necessarily the best
and wisest of those who did think about those topics) is a gross distortion of
the historical reality of the Atlantic world of those times.
Paine came to people’s
attention in America because of Common
Sense and other essays he wrote once he landed in America. However, there are
likely to have been many other people on both sides of the Atlantic who
understood the issues surrounding the “original right” to which Marshall
referred in his Supreme Court decision even if they never gave written voice to
their understanding concerning those issues.
Many people might
consider James Madison to be the ‘father of the Constitution’. Unfortunately, if
this is the case, then this also means that the Constitution was framed or
limited by Madison’s interpretation of the ‘original right’ to which all people
-- according to Marshall -- were entitled.
Justice Marshall believed
that it was the intent of the framers of the Constitution to generate “a
fundamental and paramount law of the nation.” Nonetheless, to claim -- as
Justice Marshall did in the Marbury v.
Madison decision – that the document constructed via the Philadelphia
Convention should be deemed to be permanent, co-opts the opportunity of many
other people to give expression to the ‘original right’ – a right which
Marshall acknowledges all people have -- in a way that is different (perhaps
substantially so) from that which was generated through the Philadelphia Convention.
According to Justice
Marshall, the theory which those who frame constitutions rely on involves the
idea that any act of a legislature which is considered “repugnant to the
constitution, is void.” Justice Marshall considers such a theory to be attached
to every written constitution, and, as a result, he feels that his court – the
Supreme Court – must treat that kind of a theory “as one of the fundamental
principles of our society.”
It is understandable that
those who frame a constitution would wish their document to be the “fundamental
and paramount law of the nation” and, therefore, they would be of the opinion
that any act of the legislation which is repugnant to that constitution should
be considered to be void. Less understandable is the idea: That those who are
to be governed by this kind of a “fundament and paramount law” would
necessarily agree that any act of the legislature – or the people – which runs
contrary to that law should be considered to be repugnant and, therefore, void.
Why favor the ideas of
those who frame constitutions over the ideas of those who do not frame
constitutions? Why should those who frame constitutions have a greater claim on
the “original right” to which Justice Marshall refers in the Marbury v. Madison decision than those
who do not frame constitutions?
Conceivably, any written
constitution that can be shown to violate the “original right” to which --
according to Chief Justice Marshall -- all people are entitled should be
considered to be repugnant with respect to that “original right”. Moreover, if
those constitutions are found to be repugnant in the foregoing sense, then
perhaps those constitutions ought to be considered void.
The most “fundamental and
paramount law of the nation” should be firmly rooted in the “original right” to
which all people are entitled. Unfortunately, Justice Marshall is assuming that
because the intent of the framers of the constitution was to accomplish such a
goal – that is, to root the law of the land (the constitution) in the ‘original
right’ – then the Supreme Court was obligated to honor that sort of an
intention and, as a result, treat the Philadelphia Constitution as permanent.
Justice Marshall never
seems to ask the following question: Notwithstanding the intention of the framers,
did they get it right? That is, did the constitution framed by the delegates to
the Philadelphia Convention give ‘proper and adequate’ expression to the
‘original right’ to which everyone is entitled?
Why treat anything as
permanent until the foregoing questions can be answered in a way that is likely
to be true beyond all reasonable doubt? Why honor or adopt the theory of the
framers concerning the idea that any act of the legislature which is repugnant
to the Constitution should be considered void unless one can demonstrate beyond
a reasonable doubt that such a document is not repugnant to the ‘original
right’ to which all people are entitled?
In McCulloch
v. Maryland (1819), Justice
Marshall argued that if a constitution were to give expression to a complete
account of all the powers inherent in it as well as the means through which
such powers might be realized, then, this kind of a document could not be
grasped by the human mind and “would probably never be understood by the
public.” In the light of the foregoing practical realities, Justice Marshall
went on to claim that, as a result, constitutions were written in such a way
that only the outlines of the fundamental law were written, and the details of
such a law would be deduced from that which was written with respect to the
‘fundamental and paramount law of the nation.’
Let’s assume, for the
sake of argument, that Justice Marshall’s foregoing account is correct. What
happens if the outline provided by a given constitution does not properly
reflect the ‘original right” to which Justice Marshall believes that all people
are entitled?
Furthermore, if the
nature of a constitution distorts the ‘original right’, then what sense is to
be made of the ‘deductions’ which are supposed to provide the details that are
entailed by the general outline of the constitution? If one starts with a
flawed document, then the deductions which are made in conjunction with that
kind of document will also be flawed no matter how impeccable the logic of any
given deduction might be.
The foregoing problem is
compounded when one raises questions about whether, or not, this or that
deduction is warranted and can be demonstrated -- beyond a reasonable doubt --
to be fully consistent with the purposes for which a given constitution has
been written. For example, any deduction concerning the Constitution framed by
the participants in the Philadelphia Convention must be capable of being shown
to fully consistent with the principles/objects/purposes that are being
advanced in the Preamble to the Constitution.
Thus, any given deduction
of detail drawn from the general outline of the Philadelphia Constitution must
be capable of demonstrating – beyond a reasonable doubt – how such a deduction
gives expression to: ‘perfecting the union,’ ‘establishing justice,’ ‘insuring
tranquility,’ ‘providing for the common defense,’ ‘providing for the general
welfare,’ and ‘securing the blessings of liberty.’ Moreover, the foregoing
sorts of deductions must advance all the goals and purposes of the Preamble
simultaneously and to an equal degree (there is no ‘either-or’ in the
Preamble). Otherwise, the reason for which the constitution purportedly was
framed will not be served.
In addition, if, as
Justice Marshall claimed earlier, the public would never be able to understand
a constitution that contained a complete account of all the powers inherent in
a constitution together with the variety of means for realizing those powers,
why should one suppose that the public will understand the character of the deductions
made by a given court concerning that kind of a document? Any deduction – even
though it is nothing more than a detail – must be capable of being shown to be
consonant with the constitution if it were written out in its full reality, or
it is not a valid deduction
Like a chess player who
sees the moves of a game to its conclusion (e.g., at a certain point in his
career, Bobby Fischer claimed to be this sort of a player), presumably a jurist
should be capable of seeing how a given deduction is consistent with the
meaning of the constitution if it were to be fully elaborated in terms of all
its powers, means, goals, and objects. If a jurist could not do this, then one
wonders about the validity of the deduction that such an individual is making
with respect to the alleged meaning of the constitution.
In light of the foregoing
considerations, one might question whether any jurist -- let alone the public --
has that sort of understanding of a constitution. However, if the public cannot
understand the nature of the constitution – whether written in a complete form,
or written in a manner in which certain deductions were said to be consistent
with such a fully elaborated document – then, what is one to make of Justice
Marshall’s belief that the words of the constitution are to be understood as
meaning what the general public understood by such words, as well as what the
general public meant with respect to the relation of those words to one
another?
One implication of
Justice Marshall’s foregoing argument is that constructions such as the
“necessary and proper” clause allude to principles that are present implicitly
in the constitution even if not explicitly mentioned in that document. In other
words, because one could not possibly provide an explicit list of all the
powers, means, and objects to which the “necessary and proper” clause is
capable of giving expression, then the three word clause is the linguistic
portal through which all sorts of implicit realities might emerge by means of
an appropriate deduction.
Many people seem to be
under the impression that the “necessary and proper” clause is about what
government requires in order to be able to function effectively. However, that
clause is embedded in a context – namely, the Preamble to the Constitution –
and, therefore, the aforementioned clause is not, strictly speaking, just a
matter of effective government without qualification, but, rather, the
“necessary and proper” clause is about the exercise of effective governance
with respect to the realization of: ‘a more perfect union,’ ‘justice,’
‘tranquility,’ ‘defense,’ ‘welfare,’ and ‘liberty.’
Even if one were to argue
that the “necessary and proper” clause should be understood in terms of the
enumerated powers of Article I, Section 8, whatever deductions were made would
have to be filtered through the purposes set forth in the Preamble. Thus, the
capacity of the legislature to: “lay and collect taxes, duties, imposts, and
excises” must be pursued not only to: “provide for the common defense and
general welfare of the United States,” but, as well, to: ‘insure domestic
tranquility,’ ‘establish justice,’ ‘secure the blessings of liberty,’ and ‘to
form a more perfect union.’ However, one cannot do any of the foregoing unless
on can demonstrate, beyond a reasonable doubt, what is meant by: ‘welfare,’
‘tranquility,’ ‘defense’, ‘justice,’ ‘liberty,’ and ‘perfection’ … words for
which neither the general public, nor jurists, have any agreed upon
understanding – either individually or in conjunction with one another.
The other powers that are
enumerated in Article I, Section 8 – such as: borrowing money, regulating
commerce, coining money, declaring war, raising and supporting armies – are
subject to the same kinds of constraints as outlined above. In other words, all
of the powers mentioned in Article I, Section 8 must be viewed through the
lenses of the purposes and objects of the Preamble, as well as be reconciled
with those purposes and objects.
Finally, having just any
theory of what constitutes: ‘a more perfect union,’ ‘justice,’ ‘tranquility,’
‘defense,’ ‘welfare,’ and ‘liberty,’ will not do. The standard against which those
purposes must be measured will be a function of the ‘original right’ to which
Justice Marshall referred in Marbury v.
Madison.
If the relationship is
flawed between, on the one hand, the “fundamental and paramount law of the
nation” – i.e., the constitution – and, on the other hand, the ‘original right’
to which everyone is entitled, then, this will lead to a variety of problems.
These problems range from: a failure to properly understand the meaning of the
purposes and objects of the Preamble, to: making invalid deductions concerning
the details of how such objects and purposes are to be translated into concrete
actions via the procedural powers and means of the constitution.
Justice Marshall assumes
that all of the foregoing issues have been properly resolved, and, as a result,
he contends, as previously pointed out, that the courts have an obligation to
treat the procedural provisions of the Philadelphia Constitution as permanent
inhabitants of the legal landscape. In order to satisfy the indicated
obligation, Justice Marshall believes the only thing that jurists must do to
arrive at the appropriate deductions is to juxtapose real world cases next to
the “fundamental and paramount law of the nation.”
Unfortunately, Justice
Marshall offers no proof that his assumption concerning any of the foregoing is
justified beyond a reasonable doubt. What Marshall takes to be settled law is
not as settled as he supposes it to be, and, consequently, many, if not most,
of Justice Marshall’s decisions were skewed by the biases that were inherent in
his assumption concerning the presumed legitimacy and settled character of the
Philadelphia Constitution.
At the very least, there
can be no obligation to treat a framed constitution as permanent unless one can
demonstrate that such a document gives appropriate – and, therefore,
justifiable – expression to the ‘original right’ from which such a document is
supposedly derived. In the absence of that sort of proof, there can be no sense
of obligation at all, and, therefore, Justice Marshall sought to impose on the
courts an obligation which neither he nor the framers could demonstrate, beyond
a reasonable doubt, necessarily reflected an accurate rendering of the
‘original right’ to which all people are entitled.
In McCulloch v. Maryland, Justice Marshall emphasized the importance
which considerations involving intentions played in arriving at appropriate
constructions concerning the meaning of the Constitution. For example, he
indicated that, presumably, one of the intentions of the framers was to make
appropriate provisions for linking the execution of certain powers with that
which would enhance the national welfare.
The foregoing
understanding might be true … that is, one could accept the idea – for the sake
of argument -- that the framers did intend that whatever powers were contained
in the Constitution were to be applied for purposes of promoting the general
welfare. However, until one understands what the nature of the general welfare
is and whether, or not, the exercise of a certain power in a particular way
will bring about that kind of an enhancement in the general welfare without
affecting other aspects of society in a problematic way – for example, in a way
that undermines: justice, liberty, tranquility, and defense -- then the
intentions of the framers are neither here nor there.
What is relevant,
however, is that irrespective of what the intentions of the framers might have
been, one needs to know the nature of the relationship between the exercise of
a given power and what such an exercise has to do with the ‘original right’ to
which, according to Justice Marshall, we are all entitled. One cannot use the intentions
of the framers as a starting point for interpretive deliberations, but,
instead, one needs to start from the nature of the ‘original right’ which –
according to Justice Marshall -- has precedence over the intentions of the
framers since the intentions of the framers are only relevant to the extent
that their understanding gives proper expression to the ‘original right.’
Justice Marshall argued
in Dartmouth College v. Woodward (1819)
that when a given rule is applied to a case, then, under normal circumstances,
the words of that rule should control that application. The exception to the
foregoing would be in those instances in which “the literal construction is so
obviously absurd, or mischievous, or repugnant to the general spirit of the
instrument, as to justify those who expound the constitution in making it an
exception.”
Dartmouth College v. Woodward is viewed by Justice Marshall through the lenses
of the idea of a contract. In fact, several of Justice Marshall’s fellow
justices – Justice Story and Justice Washington -- devoted considerable effort
in their concurring opinions attempting to demonstrate that the agreement
between New Hampshire and Dartmouth College was contractual in nature.
Even the state government
of New Hampshire considered the aforementioned agreement to be a contract.
However, it wanted to construe the agreement in a way that placed the agreement
outside of the purview of the contract clause of the Philadelphia Constitution
… either in the sense that such agreements were not what the Founders/Framers
had in mind when they introduced the contract clause into the Constitution, or
in the sense that the idea of a charter fell beyond the horizons of the
contract clause and, therefore, the latter did not apply to the issue of charters.
Justice Marshall argued:
“Does public policy so imperiously demand their charter at issue remaining
exposed to legislative alteration, as to compel us, or rather permit us, to say
that these words [he is referring to the contract clause] which were introduced
to give stability to contract, and which in their plain import comprehend this
contract, must be so construed as to exclude it?” A short while later, Justice
Marshall adds: “Do such contracts so necessarily require new modeling by the
authority of the legislature that the ordinary rules of construction must be
disregarded…?”
There is an issue
involving the meaning of words in Dartmouth
College v. Woodward, but that issue is not necessarily what Justice
Marshall (or Washington and Story) supposed it was – namely, one of contracts.
The term “charter” appears in the foregoing extract from Justice Marshall’s
decision concerning Dartmouth College v.
Woodward (as well in the New Hampshire arguments concerning the matter),
and although a considerable segment of several of the judicial opinions
concerning Dartmouth College v. Woodward
are devoted to arguments that purport to demonstrate how the idea of contracts
is relevant to the aforementioned case, one might raise the question of
whether, or not, a charter actually constitutes a contract.
Charters might be sought
by those wishing to be granted a charter, and the granters of charters might
seek an appropriate recipient upon whom to bestow a given charter. However,
charters are not offered in a contractual sense.
Charters are permissions
with conditions. They are granted by an individual or individuals in power, not
offered.
In order for the law of
contracts to be applied, one must demonstrate that the three basic elements of
a contract are present – that is, offer, acceptance, and consideration.
Charters do not contain the element of ‘offer’, and, therefore, they are not
contracts.
One can, of course, try
to force-fit the idea of a charter into the language of contracts by claiming
that whatever social and verbal interaction which take place between the one
granting a charter and the recipient of that kind of a charter constitutes some
form of offer and acceptance, or that there is an element of consideration
present in the granting of a charter since both the one who grants a charter
and the one who is granted a charter might enjoy benefits from that sort of a
relationship. However, the foregoing way of rendering the idea of a charter is
distortive because it completely overlooks the asymmetric character of the
relationship between the one who grants a charter and the one who is granted a
charter.
To be sure, the party
which is granted a charter might, in time, become so powerful that it can
leverage its position to change the nature of the relationship and, thereby,
come to dominate, in various ways, the one who originally granted the charter.
However, the foregoing possibility does not alter the fact that at its
inception, a charter was granted by one in power and could, in time, be revoked
by that same power.
There is no element of
offer in a charter. It is either granted or it is not, and no one has a right
to be the recipient of such a grant -- or continue to benefit from such a grant
-- by virtue of either a form of acceptance or form of consideration.
To try to construe
charters as contracts is – to use the language of Justice Marshall - - to
generate a “construction so obviously absurd, or mischievous, or repugnant to
the general spirit of the instrument” [that is, a charter] that one is
justified in arguing that the contract clause of the Constitution is not an
appropriate rule to apply to such an instrument … not because the idea of a
charter is an exception to the rule in relation to the issue of contracts but
because charters do not constitute contracts at all.
Charters can be granted
and revoked at any time at the pleasure of the one who controls the ability to
grant charters. Whatever problems arise from the granting or revoking of such a
charter will be a matter to be sorted out through the laws governing torts
and/or power politics and not through the laws of contracts.
While it might be true –
as Justice Marshall claimed – that the contract clause was intended to give
stability to contracts, this point is irrelevant to the issuing of charters. The
fact that Justice Marshall construed charters as a form of contract merely
indicates there were problems surrounding the meaning of words such as
‘contract’ and ‘charter.’
A great deal of mischief
has been introduced into society through the confusion which Justice Marshall –
and those who concurred with him -- established as a precedent in the form of
the Supreme Court decision concerning Dartmouth
College v. Woodward. Like the erroneous claim involving the alleged
personhood of corporations that was illegitimately associated with the 1886
Supreme Court decision involving Santa
Clara County v. The Southern Pacific Railroad, the Dartmouth College v. Woodward decision has been used by
corporations to gain unjustified and unwarranted control over various aspects
of social and economic life to the disadvantage of actual living human beings.
In Article I, Section 10,
Paragraph 1, the Constitution stipulates that no state shall pass “any law
impairing the obligation of contracts.” Nevertheless, irrespective of whether
one interprets the idea of charters in a contractual or a non-contractual
sense, one cannot consider the idea of a contract as an entity unto itself.
The federal government
cannot do anything which would interfere with certain kinds of obligation that
are entailed by the idea of a contract within the context of a constitutional
system. More specifically, the obligation of all contracts within the United
States is to serve the purposes and objects for which the Philadelphia
Constitution allegedly had been created.
If any given contract
will not advance the purposes of tranquility, welfare, justice, defense, and
liberty, then such a contract is not fulfilling the obligation which it has to
the very document which makes that contract possible. The obligation of
contracts cannot be limited to merely the issues involving offer, acceptance
and consideration between, or among, a limited group of individuals, but,
rather, there is a dimension of obligation entailed by contracts within the
United States that must extend to the rest of society.
Whatever the intention of
the framers might have been with respect to the meaning of the contract clause
of Article I, Section 10, the deciding factor with respect to the legitimacy of
any contract is rooted in the nature of the ‘original right’ to which,
according to Justice Marshall, all people are entitled. The intention of the
framers only becomes relevant if that intention reflects the structural
character of the ‘original right’ since all contracts – as is also true with
respect to every other aspect of governance -- must be evaluated in terms of
the requirements of that ‘right.’
One can impair the
obligation of contracts in the limited sense (that is, in terms of the contract
considered on its own) under certain circumstances. For instance, if the
aforementioned ‘lesser’ sense of obligation impairs the purposes for which the
Constitution was established (which are outlined in the Preamble), and/or if
the lesser sense of obligation impairs people’s ability to realize the
‘original right’ to which Justice Marshall says everyone is entitled, then
there is basis for interfering with contracts made under the foregoing sorts of
conditions. In short, contracts – in the foregoing lesser sense -- must adhere
to a larger obligation involving the purposes of the Constitution and/or the
requirements of the ‘original right’ to which all people are entitled.
So, to answer what Justice Marshall
seemed to consider a rhetorical question in his decision concerning Dartmouth College v. Woodward – namely:
“Does public policy so imperiously demand their charter at issue remaining
exposed to legislative alteration, as to compel us, or rather permit us, to say
that these words [he is referring to the contract clause] which were introduced
to give stability to contract, and which in their plain import comprehend this
contract, must be so construed as to exclude it?” – the answer is: ‘yes’ …
although one could dispense with Marshall’s judgmental use of such words as:
”imperiously.”
The words of the contract
clause might have been introduced in order to lend stability to contracts, but
the Philadelphia Constitution was introduced – and, here, we will give the
benefit of a doubt to the intentions of the participants in the Philadelphia
Convention without necessarily supposing that what they did, or the way in
which they did it, was legitimate – to stabilize the social/political/economic
context in which contracts, among other things, are rooted. Therefore, if any
given contract should entail ramifications that are likely to destabilize the
purposes for which the Constitution was established or which will deny people
access to the ‘original right’ to which they are entitled, then the lesser
obligations of that kind of a contract are no longer tenable in the light of
the greater obligation that all contracts have with respect to either the
purposes for which the Philadelphia Constitution was instituted and/or the
‘original right’ to which all people are entitled.
In McCulloch v. Maryland (1819), Justice Marshall joined the
‘necessary and proper’ clause with the ‘supremacy clause’ to rule that: (a) the
idea of a national bank was constitutional and (b) Maryland had no right to tax
a branch of that bank in order to undermine the national bank’s viability. More
specifically, on the one hand, the ‘necessary and proper’ clause was used to
indicate that even though the idea of a national bank had not been mentioned in
the Constitution, Justice Marshall was of the opinion that such a bank was both
a necessary and proper means through which to realize the purposes of
governance, while, on the other hand, the supremacy clause was invoked to argue
that since the idea of a national bank was perfectly constitutional, laws
establishing it were part of the supreme law of the land and, therefore, states
– in this case, Maryland – had to comply with those laws.
Although the general
idea of a national bank might be constitutional, it does not necessarily follow
that the particular way in which a given form of national bank might be
envisioned to operate would also be constitutional. If the operating principles
of that sort of bank: did not establish justice, and/or did not promote the
general welfare, and/or did not secure the blessings of liberty, and/or did not
insure domestic tranquility, and/or did not help provide for the common
defense, and/or denied people access to the ‘original right’ to which everyone
was entitled, then whatever the necessary and proper character of the general
idea of a national bank might be with respect to the issue of governance, then
nevertheless, the foregoing sort of a bank would be unconstitutional with
respect to the purposes for which the Constitution was established and from
which the Constitution supposedly derived its authority.
While the laws passed by
the legislature might be interpreted to be constitutional and, as a result,
understood to be part of the supreme law of the land with which individuals and
states supposedly must comply, the Philadelphia Constitution really has never
been proven – beyond a reasonable doubt – to be the supreme law for human
beings and, therefore, such laws are entirely arbitrary. Making the claim of
supremacy is not necessarily the same thing as being able to demonstrate,
beyond a reasonable doubt, that those claims are likely to be an accurate
reflection of the nature of reality.
As previous chapters of
this book have indicated: The legitimacy of the origins of the Philadelphia
Constitution is questionable, and the legitimacy of the ratification process associated
with that constitution is questionable, and the purposes and meanings of the
Philadelphia Constitution are questionable and the claim of legitimacy
concerning the claim that such a constitution is obligatory upon those who did
not draft it and did not authorize it is also questionable. In addition, the
relation of the Philadelphia Constitution to the ‘original right’ to which all
human beings are entitled is also questionable.
With so many issues of:
Legitimacy, purposes, and meanings that are considered to be questionable, how
can one claim that laws which are understood by some jurists to be
constitutional should be considered the supreme law of the land? How do we know
– beyond a reasonable doubt – that those jurists or judges have not been operating
in accordance with judicial will rather than in accordance with the sorts of
judicial judgments that, presumably, should be able to be justified beyond a
reasonable doubt?
Justice Marshall deduced
– in a very narrow sense -- that the general idea of a national bank was
permissible as an expression of the ‘necessary and proper clause. Justice
Marshall did not consider – in a much broader sense -- whether, or not, the
actual manner in which that bank operated could also be deduced to be necessary
and proper.
In McCulloch v. Maryland, Justice Marshall failed to address an issue
that was much more fundamental and in need of critical examination – namely,
how the national bank actually works and affects – in practical terms -- the
purposes for which the Constitution was instituted. Instead, Justice Marshall
considered only superficial issues – for example, whether, or not, the general
idea of a national bank could be considered to be necessary and proper.
By pursuing the
superficial at the expense of the substantial, Justice Marshall established a
precedent that has led to much mischief. In effect, Justice Marshall showed how
one could engage the Constitution through, for instance, the “necessary and
proper” clause or the “supremacy” clause without ever raising the question of
how – or if -- such clauses were actually serving the purposes of the Preamble
or whether, or not, any given interpretation of those clauses could be
reconciled with the ‘original right’ to which he believed everyone was
entitled.
To claim that the general
idea of a national bank is consistent with, or deducible from, the “necessary
and proper” clause is an extremely trivial matter. The existential impact of an
operating national bank upon the purposes set forth in the Preamble and upon the
lives of ‘We the People’ is an entirely different matter.
Without necessarily
wishing to take Maryland’s side in the dispute with McCulloch (a cashier in the
Baltimore branch of the 2nd National Bank who issued bank notes
contrary to laws of the state of Maryland), one could raise the question of
whose actions – if either -- best served the purposes of the Constitution.
Justice Marshall might not have wanted to deal with this sort of a question,
but by addressing only the superficial issue about whether, or not, the general
idea of a national bank was constitutional, he evaded one of the few issues of
potentially substantive value in McCulloch
v. Maryland.
Furthermore, Justice
Marshall also evaded the question of whether, or not, it was possible for one party
– e.g., Maryland – to violate what were considered to be constitutionally valid
laws and, therefore, part of the supreme law of the land, and yet nonetheless,
in so doing, serve the purposes of the Preamble in a more defensible manner
than the actions, policies and programs of the federal government did. This
kind of question has implications for, among other things, the issue of civil
disobedience and, in the process, raises the question of whose actions best
serve the purposes for which the Constitution was supposedly instituted or
whose actions best serve the ‘original right’ to which all people are entitled.
Two of the grounds for
the decision in the McCulloch v. Maryland
case revolved about: (1) whether the potential for the power to tax entailed the
power to destroy, and (2) the commonsensical precept that the people considered
as a whole could not be presumed to have ceded the sort of power indicated in
(1) above to a part of the whole – namely, a state. However, one legitimately
could apply the same sort of logic to almost every aspect of governance.
In other words, every
power – and not just the power to tax – entails the possibility of being used
in such a way that it becomes destructive. This includes the powers that are
enumerated in the Constitution.
Surely, as Justice
Marshall’s commonsensical logic stipulates, no one should be able to suppose in
any justifiable manner that the people considered as a whole have ceded such
power (that is, destructive power) to the part – the state government – so that
the latter can adversely affect the opportunity of the whole to realize the
purposes set forth in the Preamble to the Constitution. The point which Justice
Marshall is making in relation to the state of Maryland and its manner of
wielding power can be justifiably applied to the federal government and its
manner of wielding power, but Justice Marshall does not permit himself to
venture into that sort of territory because he believes – quite unjustifiably –
that those matters have, in some vague sense, been settled via the ratification
of the Philadelphia Constitution.
What is meant by:
“necessary and proper,” or “the supreme law of the land,” or “impairing the
obligation of contracts,” cannot be known until one understands what is meant
by: ‘establishing justice,’ ‘insuring domestic tranquility,’ ‘providing for the
common defense,’ ‘promoting the general welfare,’ ‘securing the blessings of
liberty’ – for ourselves and our posterity – and having access to the ‘original
right” to which everyone is entitled. No part of the Philadelphia Constitution
has a non-arbitrary sense until one can – if one can -- resolve the
hermeneutical issues surrounding the foregoing phrases in a way that can be
shown, beyond a reasonable doubt, to be accurately reflective of the nature of
reality.
The way in which Justice
Marshall framed the legal issues during his 35 years of adjudicating matters
are largely arbitrary … and this is a trend that has continued in the United
States among Supreme Court jurists for nearly two hundred more years. Those
ways are arbitrary because they never address the underlying, substantive
issues of meaning that need to be engaged in those matters … issues which have
the capacity to color, shape, and orient not only every aspect of the Constitution
but every deduction that might be made in relation to that document.
For example, consider the
commerce clause – namely, Congress shall have the power to: “regulate commerce
with foreign nations, and among the several states, and with the Indian tribes.”
In Gibbons v. Ogden (1825) Justice
Marshall described the power to regulate commerce as being fairly
comprehensive, involving the capacity: “To prescribe the rule by which commerce
is to be governed.” Furthermore, Marshall defined commerce broadly to encompass
all facets of the dynamics among nations, the states, and Indian tribes
involving the selling, buying and transporting of goods.
There were, however,
several limits to the power of the federal government with respect to the
regulation of commerce. One limit concerned the right of states to regulate
whatever commerce took place entirely within a given state and, therefore, did
not spill over into, or become entangled with the commercial activity of other
states.
The other limit on
federal authority to regulate commerce was a function of those police powers
within a state that might have incidental -- but, nonetheless significant --
impact on commercial activity. For example, laws touching upon matters
involving health, inspection, and the like in relation to commercial activity
were considered to be under the purview of the states … although Marshall was
inclined to place limits on just how much of this sort of incidental impact
would be permitted.
While Justice Marshall
dealt with the definition of commerce, as well as with what the idea of
regulation involved, he was largely silent about the purpose of such regulation
– other than that it was one of the powers granted to Congress by the
Constitution. However, like every other aspect of Constitution, the lens
through which the words of that document should be considered are the purposes
set forth in the Preamble for which the Constitution was supposedly ordained
and established.
Just as the states must
operate within a commercial framework that is determined through the federal
government’s power to regulate the rules governing the operation of that
framework, so too, the federal government must exercise its powers within a
framework that is regulated by the purposes for which the Constitution came into
being. Unfortunately, if the nature of those purposes is indeterminate, then so
too, is the nature of the commercial regulatory power that is to be exercised
by the federal government.
One cannot deduce very
much with respect to the nature of the regulatory power of the federal
government until one understands the logical or structural character of the
purposes set forth in the Preamble. Until one understands what the regulation
of commerce has to do with issues such as: justice, liberty, tranquility, defense,
and the general welfare, then without being entirely arbitrary, one is not in a
position to proceed very far beyond the very general idea that, in some unknown
sense, the federal government has the right – for the sake of argument this is
being presumed -- to regulate commerce involving foreign nations, states, and
the Indian tribes.
-----
A little over a hundred
years after Justice Marshall wrote his last opinion for the Supreme Court,
Justice Harland Stone issued a decision concerning Southern Pacific v. Arizona (1945). In the opinion for that case,
Justice Stone sought to establish a ‘balancing test’ for deciding cases
involving the commerce clause. Justice Stone’s notion of a ‘balancing test’
departed – in certain respects -- from what had been up to that time the
standard through which many kinds of commerce clause cases were often decided.
More specifically, one of
the standard precedents for commerce clause-related cases was set forth in Cooley v. Board of Wardens (1852). At
the heart of this case – which occurred during the tenure of Chief Justice
Taney -- is the issue of whether, or not, the precedent which had been
established by Chief Justice Marshall – namely, that the federal government had
a largely exclusive right (with a few exceptions) to regulate matters of
commerce in the United States – precluded the possibility of states having
control over the regulation of commerce in certain cases … e.g., those
involving pilotage laws.
The Cooley v. Board of Wardens case involved a law in Pennsylvania that
required vessels coming into the Port of Philadelphia to use local pilots. If
incoming ships did not use local pilots, then the owners of those vessels would
be required to pay half the cost of pilotage … a fee that went into a fund
intended to help pilots through difficult economic times, as well as to assist
them after they retired.
The Supreme Court ruled
that the foregoing law was constitutional despite the fact it intruded into the
area of regulating commerce … an area that was, for the most part, under the
purview of the federal government. Just as Justice Marshall previously had
indicated that there were exceptions to the commerce clause – e.g., commercial
activity taking place wholly within the confines of a given state -- so too,
Justice Curtis ruled in the Cooley v.
Board of Wardens decision that while, generally speaking, the federal
government did have the authority to regulate commerce, there were various
anomalous situations – such as in the case of pilotage – in which states shared
a legitimate, concurrent power with the federal government with respect to the
regulation of commerce.
Justice Curtis indicated
in his decision that when it came to establishing national rules of uniformity
concerning certain facets of commerce, the federal government should have the
preeminent authority to regulate commerce. However, some aspects of commerce
reflected local conditions, and in the latter cases, state governments had a
valid standing with respect to certain claims concerning the regulation of
commerce according to the requirements of those local circumstances.
The foregoing decision
was not really a departure from what Justice Marshall had established in, for
example, Gibbons v. Ogden (1825). In
fact, in the latter decision, Justice Marshall had specifically referred to
pilots operating within the “bays, inlets, rivers, harbors, and ports” of
certain states and how the regulating of such commercial activity fell within
the purview of states.
According to Justice
Stone’s opinion in the 1945 Southern
Pacific v. Arizona case his reading of the earlier 1852 Cooley v. Board of Wardens decision was
that the Supreme Court was the final arbiter when it came to adjudicating
conflicting demands involving national and state interests in those cases where
Congress had not passed any relevant legislation. Justice Stone, then, sought
to establish a ‘balancing test’ through which the Court would seek to weigh the
relative impact of state and national interests upon the “free flow of
interstate commerce” in those sorts of cases.
The opinions in: Southern Pacific v. Arizona, Cooley v. Board of Wardens and Gibbons v. Ogden – spanning a period of
125 years – were all off the mark. The Supreme Court, as well as the federal
and state governments, did not have any authority to arbitrate issues of
commercial activity independently of either the purposes and objects of the
Preamble to the Constitution, or the ‘original right’ noted by Justice Marshall
in Marbury v. Madison.
The issue of commercial
activity is not one of weighing the impact of state and national interests upon
the ‘free flow of interstate commerce.’ The issue of commercial activity is not
a matter of when the Court could arbitrate cases involving commercial activity
(e.g., when Congress had not passed any relevant legislation). The issue of
commercial activity is not a function of divvying up the spheres of influence
over which the federal and state governments should have preeminent regulatory
authority.
Instead, the issue is --
and should have been -- entirely a matter of when, or if, commercial activity
serves the principles inherent in the Preamble to the Constitution and/or the
‘original right’ to which Justice Marshall referred … principles and purposes
that, supposedly, were the means through which the United States of America was
to become established as a democratic nation on the world stage in the first
place. If, for example, commercial activity does not simultaneously further –
in a way that is demonstrable beyond a reasonable doubt -- the principles of
justice, tranquility, welfare, and liberty for all of the people in the
United States, then neither the Court, the federal government, the states, nor
anyone else has a legitimate – that is, justifiable – constitutional right to
regulate commerce for any other purposes.
Alternatively, if
commercial activity does not instantiate Justice Marshall’s notion of an
‘original right’ in a manner that is capable of being demonstrated beyond a
reasonable doubt as likely to reflect the actual ‘original right’ that is
inherent in all human existence, then neither the Court, the federal
government, the states, nor anyone else has a legitimate – that is, justifiable
– right to regulate commercial activity. The foregoing does not mean that
individuals have the right to do whatever they like with respect to commercial
activity, for such individuals -- like the judicial, executive, and legislative
branches of the federal government, as well as the members of state and local
governments – must be able to demonstrate, beyond a reasonable doubt, that they
have the right to act commercially in one way rather than another, or the
arguments of those individuals are as arbitrary as the ones which are employed
by governments … whether national, state, or local.
As noted previously, in Marbury v. Madison Justice Marshall had
referred to an ‘original right” to which all people were entitled. He assumed –
unjustifiably (i.e., he did not demonstrate that his assumption was capable of
being proven beyond a reasonable doubt) – that such a right was necessarily
embodied in, and expressed through, the Philadelphia Constitution.
In their respective
decisions, Justice Curtis and Justice Stone (each in his own way) assumed --
unjustifiably (i.e., they did not demonstrate that their assumptions concerning
the supposed authority, and, therefore, source of obligation of the
Constitution were true beyond a reasonable doubt) -- that their judicial
opinions should be incumbent upon, or binding on, others (the executive, the
legislature, the state governments, and citizens). In other words, neither of
the two justices was able to successfully show that the Supreme Court had the
authority to determine what the meaning of the Philadelphia Constitution was
with respect to, on the one hand, the general principles and purposes set forth
in the Preamble, or in relation to the ‘original right’ to which Justice
Marshall alluded in Marbury v. Madison,
and, on the other hand, commercial activity.
The executive,
legislative, and judicial branches of the federal government, as well as the
state governments all assume that they have the requisite authority to
interpret the meaning of the Philadelphia Constitution, the Preamble, and the
‘original right’ in ways that are binding on citizens. None of them, however, have been able
to demonstrate the legitimacy of those claims to authority beyond a reasonable
doubt.
The source of legitimate
authority is not a function of superficial issues of procedural jurisdiction –
irrespective of whether those deliberations are the result of interpretive
efforts by the executive, legislative, and judicial branches, or state and
local governments – in relation to some given constitutional document. The
source of legitimate – that is, non-arbitrary – authority is a function of substantive
issues concerning what is, and what is not, demonstrable beyond a reasonable
doubt with respect to the nature of reality.
Justices legislate – and,
therefore, exercise judicial will rather than judgment – whenever their
decisions cannot be shown, beyond a reasonable doubt, to be capable of demonstrating that those opinions reflect
the nature of reality with respect to issues such as: rights, liberty, justice,
and welfare, or with respect to ‘the meanings’ of any of the crucial clauses of
the Philadelphia Constitution -- e.g., commerce clause, contract clause,
supremacy clause, due process clause, or the necessary and proper clause –
relative to the ‘original right’ to which we all are entitled
When justices legislate
from the bench – that is, exercise judicial will -- their decisions are
arbitrary. In other words, their claims concerning those decisions cannot be
justified as giving expression to defensible interpretations of various
fundamental principles, meanings, and purposes of democracy … i.e.,
interpretations which can demonstrate, beyond a reasonable doubt, that their
claims to authority -- with respect to placing obligations on the citizenry in
relation to expectations concerning compliance with the ‘rule of law’ that is
alleged to be inherent in a given constitution -- are legitimate.
Unfortunately, for more
than 225 years, Supreme Court justices in the United States have been engaged
in one arbitrary exercise of judicial review after another when it comes to
their engagement of the Philadelphia Constitution, along with the amendments
which, in subsequent years, were added to that document. As a result, we are
governed by the arbitrary conventions of men, and, now, women – that is,
individuals exercising judicial will -- rather than by the rule of law in any
non-arbitrary sense.
None of the foregoing
considerations should be construed to mean that judges don’t employ reasoned
arguments in order to arrive at their conclusions in relation to this or that
case. As they construct their judicial position, they cite precedents – many of
which have a questionable pedigree as far as the purposes and principles of the
Preamble and/or Marshall’s ‘original right’ are concerned -- and refer,
approvingly or disapprovingly, to the arguments of this or that jurist, as well
as parse the language of the case before them in terms of those facets of the
Constitution which they consider to be relevant to the case before them
In addition, over time,
their arguments often exhibit consistency and coherency. As a result, one can
see that many jurists have a style of arguing and an inclination to go in
certain judicial directions rather than others.
However, being able to
put forth reasoned arguments of a coherent, consistent, and logical nature does
not guarantee that those arguments will give expression to truths concerning
the ultimate nature of liberty, rights, justice, and welfare in a way that can
be demonstrated beyond a reasonable doubt. People deserve more than arbitrary
theories, perspectives, and ideas when those possibilities are likely to have a
major impact on their basic sovereignty.
The role of citizens
should not be one of serving as experimental subjects for the theoreticians of
governance. If it is unethical: To perform psychological experiments on people
without their fully informed consent, or to perform experiments on citizens
which could be injurious to their physical, emotional, psychological, economic,
and/or spiritual health, then why should the standards of ethical activity be
any different in the realm of governance where the stakes are likely to be much
higher, as well as likely to be much more permanently debilitating, in one way
or another, with respect to citizens.
Consequently -- as
previously indicated -- the reason for setting the judicial bar so high (that
is, requiring jurists to be able to demonstrate that their opinions are likely
to be true beyond a reasonable doubt) is to hold the courts accountable in the
same way that constitutionally mandated criminal trials hold the justice system
accountable. In other words, in criminal cases, the possible consequences for a
defendant who is found guilty are fairly severe with respect to the manner in
which liberty, welfare, and tranquility might be adversely affected, and,
therefore, the standard for convicting someone requires that all twelve jurors
must find, “beyond a reasonable doubt,” that the state has met its burden of
proof concerning the issue of guilt.
Similarly, with respect
to judicial opinions that allegedly give expression to the meaning of the
Philadelphia Constitution, having nine jurists all agree that such-and-such is
the proper interpretation of that document is not enough. Such agreement must
be established beyond a reasonable doubt, and, as pointed out previously, the
idea of: ‘beyond a reasonable doubt’ means that the ‘facts’ of a case must
be shown to have a demonstrably
significant relationship with the actual nature of liberty, justice, welfare,
rights, and the like … not in a theoretical, possible, practical, utilitarian,
majoritarian, or plausible manner but in an existentially substantive way that
shows how one’s interpretation of the facts of a given judicial case reflect
the actual character of the universe.
If jurists cannot meet
the foregoing standard, then they have no non-arbitrary basis through which to
justify their claims of legitimacy with respect to their judicial perspective
and, consequently, they have no business engaging in judicial review. The
‘original right’ to which John Marshall alluded in Marbury v. Madison – a right which I equate with my notion of
‘basic sovereignty’ (that is, the right to have a fair opportunity to push back
the horizons of ignorance) -- demands a much higher standard of protection than
the Supreme Court has been prepared to offer – or, in truth, has been capable
of offering -- for the last several hundred years.
No comments:
Post a Comment